Previous: A second proof of compactness for propositional logic
Next: General discussion of propositional proof systems
Up: Supplementary Text

An algorithm to find derivations of tautologies

The proof of the completeness of PC given in Theorem II.9.9 of LMCS actually provides us with a straightforward algorithm to find derivations of tautologies. If we are given a tautology then we diagram the algorithm as follows:

Thus we see the four key parts of the algorithm:

The first part requires 2n-1 steps, namely

For the second part one needs at least steps (just to apply the distributive laws). We illustrate for the case n=2. At this point our current notation becomes difficult to read, so for the rest of this subsection we switch to an abbreviated notation, namely we will use FG for , and for . Also we will (for the time being) say has higher precedence than , so means . This will allow us to dispense with many parentheses.

So we needed the first 3 steps to obtain , the first part of the procedure, and then 5 steps to put this into disjunctive normal form. Of course one may want to rewrite this so that one has the DNF-constituents ordered according to the usual ordering of the rows of a truth table, and left associated, namely as

After all, to have a DNF one needs to specify the order in which the DNF constituents are written, and how they are parenthesized. To go from line (8) above to this form will require 8 additional steps, applying commutativity and associativity (as simple replacement rules):

For larger n the second part of the algorithm explodes in the amount of work one needs to do because of the exponential lower bound on the number of steps given above. For n=5 variables this is already 56 steps, i.e., at least a page of work. And we still have the third part to worry about. This can be the wild card. If F is almost in DNF then there will not be much work to do. But it can be the most tedious part of the algorithm.

Let us return to the two examples that we presented after defining the notion of derivation (on page 76) and apply the above algorithm to them, and compare the results with our earlier derivations.

Example 1 (See Example II.9.5.)
The following uses the above algorithm to derive .

This compares quite favorably to the derivation in Example II.9.5, requiring only 1 more step. Part 1 and part 2 of the algorithm collapse into the first step above. Reading steps 1 through 6, in reverse order, we see the procedure for putting step 6 into its disjunctive normal form.

The following uses the algorithm to derive .

Example 2 (See Example II.9.6.)

This is rather painful when compared to the 7 line derivation in Example II.9.6. Looking over the steps we see that part 1 is steps 1-3, part 2 is steps 3-13, part 3 is steps 42-13, and part 4 is steps 13-42. In this case we see that part 3 is the most demanding of our resources.

So the moral of this section is: yes, we do have a straightforward algorithm to find derivations. But it is probably a much better idea to look for a short derivation taking advantage of the many rules available in PC. That is why we have so many more rules than are needed to prove completeness.


Previous: A second proof of compactness for propositional logic
Next: General discussion of propositional proof systems
Up: Supplementary Text

Stan Burris
Sat Feb 1 17:42:33 EST 1997